Questions 71-77
The human species is rational in essence
(or form), so vice is contrary to our nature because it follows the
sensitive aspect rather than the rational one (Q 71. 2nd). Vicious habits
stand half-way between the potential power to do something and the action
itself (3rd). A human act is sinful when it is a voluntary act that does
not conform to how things should be, so a sinful act includes not only the
word, deed, and desire, but also the form itself, which is always contrary
to God's eternal law (6th). Sin can be divided into spiritual and carnal
sins because spiritual and carnal pleasures are two different categories
(Q 72.2nd). Sin can be divided into sin against God, against oneself (i.e.
reason), and against others (i.e. the social order), though sins against
God also encompass sins against self and others, as sins against self also
includes sin against others (4th). Sin is in many ways of a piece, sins of
commission and omission overlap and can be found in the same action (6th),
as sins of thought, word, and deed, while they can be discussed
separately, really are all apart of one type of action in that they
proceed from the same motives (7th).
However, this does not mean all sins are
connected with one another since the sinner pursues contradictory
perceived goods without the ordinate simplicity of will and purpose that
the saint has (Q 73.1st). Sins that connect to an immediate misuse of the
reason are more grave than others (3rd), so carnal sins are less guilty
than spiritual sins all other things being equal. Spiritual sins are a
turning from something, for example, reason and God, while carnal sins are
a turning to something, that is a bodily impulse. Bodily impulses are
stronger, so spiritual sins should be easier to resist. Lust, however, is
more shameful in some ways than anger or theft (5th). While ignorance is a
good reason for forgiving sin and, therefore, lessens it, it doesn't
entirely excuse it or eliminate its consequences (Q 76.4th).
Some sins begin in the agent and pass into
an act, such as false teaching or murder, while other sins remain in the
agent, such as heresy or hatred. The will is, therefore, involved in sin
(Q 74.1st). Aristotle was not entirely right to say that the object of the
will is always an apparent good because passion causes us not to consider
in a particular instance what the reason knows in general to be wrong; the
passion distracts the reason, opposes it, even fetters it, thus giving the
reason contradictory distorted propositions, such as "fornication is
wrong" but "pleasure is to be pursued" (Q 77.2nd). In a
sense, every sin of passion is a sin of weakness because it is like a
disease: it derives from an unsoundness in the body and in the
desires (3rd). While it is possible to argue that passion diminishes the
sinfulness of an act because it renders it involuntary, it is also true
that the strength of the desire intensifies the will toward what is wrong,
thereby rendering it an even graver sin (6th). Sometimes reason can
overcome passion through deliberation, and sometimes passion does not
entirely hinder the reason. If however, the voluntary use of reason is
entirely removed, then a sin is neither mortal or venial (8th).
Discussion Questions
- Is sin contrary to human nature? Why or
why not?
- Are some sins worse than others? Why or
why not?
- Are carnal sins different from spiritual
ones in your own experience?
- Is Aquinas' model of passion and reason
an accurate one? Why or why not?
- Does a sin have to be voluntary to be
sinful?
Questions 90-97
Law is "a rule and measure of acts,
whereby man is induced to act or is restrained from acting" (500).
It, therefore, belongs to reason (Q 90.1st) and is directed toward the
common good of universal happiness (2nd). By necessity, then, some must be
competent to make the laws and represent the interests of the people
(3rd). If a law is rational and for the common good and made by
representatives, it follows then that for it to be in force, it must be
promulgated (i.e. Ignorance of the law is an excuse if no one
adequately informs its subjects) (4th).
There are four kinds of law: 1) eternal
law, which is the plan of Divine Reason for the universe (Q 91.1st); 2)
natural law, which is the eternal law imprinted upon us to whatever extent
our inclinations are in line with it and thereby ruled by it (2nd); 3)
human law, which is human reason seeking to make practical the natural law
(3rd); and 4) divine law, which is the revealed law that addresses what
human law can not, especially our soul's interior state before divine
judgment and salvation (4th). Divine law encompasses both the Old Law of
the Jewish Torah and the New Law of the Gospel which has superseded and
clarified its final intent (5th).
The purpose of the law is to help its
citizens acquire virtue by disposing them to it; therefore, it also
assists the virtue already infused in a person by other means. At the very
least a society's rulers must be virtuous, even if the citizens are only
so by virtue of obeying the law (Q 92.1st). Even if citizens sometimes
obey simply out of fear of punishment, they may over time grow to do so
with delight and from free-will (2nd).
The eternal law in its essence in God
cannot be known by humans, but we can know its reflection in the creation
(Q 93.2nd). In the same way, human law is derived from eternal law when it
accords with right reason, and when it doesn't, it is unjust law. However,
human law is never equal with eternal law, some laws participating to a
greater or lesser extent in the eternal (3rd). All human affairs are
subject to eternal law to the extent that reason and passion are not
distorted and darkened by sin (6th).
Natural law begins with self-evident
principles just as certain logical axioms must be self-evident to begin
with. Some are admittedly only self-evident to the wise who truly
understand the terms and concerns in question. Just as Being is
self-evident and the Good is self-evident, so is the general principle
that the good must be pursued and the evil avoided. Natural law concerns
not only the goods of self-preservation, which it shares with all things,
and the goods of bodily existence, which it shares with other animals, but
also the goods of reason, such as the desire to know God, live in a just
society, and so on (Q 94. 2nd). All virtues are to some extent prescribed
by natural law because the reason dictates these (3rd). Natural law is
concerned with practical, moral reasoning which must apply general
principles to specific circumstances. At times, the circumstances will
call for exceptions, so while the general principles never change,
particulars may call for adjustments (4th). In that sense, natural law can
change either by additions of clarification or, on occasion, by changes in
the particulars that call for a new expression of the general principle
(5th). The natural law can never be entirely abolished from the heart of
people, though sin may do so for an instance or in a more through way by
evil customs and habits (6th).
Human beings have a natural aptitude for
knowledge and virtue, but especially in the later case, considering how
the young are inclined, we need training by others--some by their
families; others, who are more prone to vice, by the law and its power to
punish (Q 95.1st). One can judge that a human law is derived from natural
law as long as it doesn't defect from nature. Something may be derived
from natural law as a set of conclusions from premises or as the
particular details being made concrete. In the second sense, they only
have force as human laws and not as also being from natural law, as those
in the first sense do (2nd). Human law ought to be framed to reflect the
majority of instances since it is concerned with the common good (Q
96.1st), and it can only address those vices which are most harmful to the
majority and which are possible for the majority to abstain from (2nd).
Likewise, it can only address those virtues directly pertaining to the
common good, even though all virtues and vices have an impact on others
(3rd). Human laws only bind a conscience if they are just. If they support
a ruler's cupidity, encourage us to idolatry, violate God's commandments,
or inflict unjust harm on subjects, they do not bind the conscience (4th).
We may break the law in cases that call for immediate remedy only (e.g.
rushing someone to the hospital), but in other cases we should wait for
the decision of the magistrate (6th). Human laws may be changed to either
perfect an earlier imperfect law or to account for changed circumstances
(Q 97.1st), but we should not do this often since it tends to lessen
respect for the custom and authority behind the law (2nd).
Discussion Questions
- Is ignorance of the law an excuse? Why
or why not?
- What distinguishes eternal from divine
law and human law from natural law?
- Do human beings actually have a natural
law implanted in them? What does it look like? Do all share it
equally?
- Can you legislate morality? If so, how
effective can you expect to be?
- How do we know if human laws are subject
to "right reason"?
- What makes natural law according to Aquinas
different from biologically-based (or psychologically-based) legal
reasoning?
- When can a law be disobeyed? When should it be
changed?
|